Intelligent Agent Foundations Forumsign up / log in
Reflective Probability Distributions and Standard Models of Arithmetic
post by Kaya Stechly 808 days ago | Abram Demski, Jessica Taylor and Patrick LaVictoire like this | discuss

Thanks to Benya for the result and to Rafael for helping write this. This result is included in the latest draft of the new Definability of Truth paper.

Working in the framework presented in Definability of Truth, we prove that every reflective, coherent \(\mathbb{P}\) is supported only on non-standard models. We construct a finitely additive measure over the language which is supported on standard models and satisfies many of our desiderata. This shows that \(\mathbb{P}\)’s non-standard support is a direct result of requiring countable additivity.


Background

Note that some of the notation has changed from Definability of Truth: \(\mathbb{P}(\varphi)\) is written as \(\mathbb{P}[\varphi]\). This is to distinguish this as a function from the language to the reals, whereas \(\mathbb{P}(A)\), for some \(A\), is a function from the powerset of the set of all theories to the reals. Benya has shown that \(\mathbb{P}[\varphi]=\mathbb{P}(\{T:\varphi\in T\})\), so we abuse notation and use the same symbol for both functions.

We now write \(P\) for the inner language symbol instead of \(\mathbb{P}\), as they are importantly different entities. Recall that \(\mathbb{P}\) is a function from the language to \([0,1]\), and is a function in the metalanguage. We have modified the definition of \(P\) sufficiently that we discuss it in the next section.

\(P\) as a three place relation

Since we are now working in the realm of Peano arithmetic, we can weaken our definition of our inner probability distribution. Instead of defining \(P\) as a function in the language, it is sufficient for \(P\) to be a three place relation which arbitrarily approximates some metalanguage function.

Definition 1. Let \(L'\) be the extension of the language \(L\) (which contains at least the language of arithmetic) by a relation symbol \(P\). A standard theory is a complete theory over \(L'\) which extends the theory of the standard natural numbers (over \(L\)) and satisfies the following two conditions: \(P\subset\mathbb{N}^3\) and \[\exists f : L'\rightarrow[0, 1] \text{ s.t. } \forall \varphi~\forall a, b\in\mathbb{Q}: P(\dot a,\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner, \dot b) \iff f(\varphi) \in (a, b).\]

Intuitively, \(P\) is a three-valued relation which approximates some function \(f\) arbitrarily well. We imagine \(P(\dot a,\ulcorner\varphi\urcorner,\dot b)\) to mean that \(a<f(\varphi)<b\), where \(f\) is the function that we require to exist above.

Disbelief in Standard Theories

We would like to construct coherent, reflective distributions which are supported on standard theories of Peano Arithmetic. We prove that not only do such distributions not exist, but every coherent, reflective distribution must assign zero probability to any set of standard theories.

Theorem 1. Let \(T\) be a consistent theory which extends Peano Arithmetic. Let \(\mathbb{P}\) be a coherent, reflective probability distribution over \(T\). Then, \(\mathbb{P}\) must assign probability zero to any set of standard theories of \(T\).

Proof. Consider the sentence \(G\) defined by \(G \iff P(-\dot 1,\ulcorner G\urcorner,\dot 1)\). Then, \(\mathbb{P}(G)=1\). Applying the reflection principle, we get that \[\forall\epsilon>0: \mathbb{P}(\{T:P(\dot 1-\dot \epsilon,\ulcorner G\urcorner,\dot 1)\in T\})=\dot 1.\] Now, \[\{T:\forall \epsilon>0,P(\dot 1-\dot \epsilon,\ulcorner G\urcorner,\dot 1)\in T\}\] \[=\bigcap_{\epsilon>0}\{T:P(\dot 1-\dot \epsilon,\ulcorner G\urcorner,\dot 1)\in T\},\] so we apply countable additivity and De Morgan’s laws to get that \[\mathbb{P}(\{T:\forall \dot\epsilon>0,P(\dot 1-\dot \epsilon,\ulcorner G\urcorner,\dot 1)\in T\})=1.\]

This means that \(\mathbb{P}\) assigns probability zero to any set of theories which do not prove that \(\forall \epsilon>0,P(\dot 1-\dot \epsilon,\ulcorner G\urcorner,\dot 1)\). In particular, no standard theory can prove this statement, as otherwise it would contain a number smaller than one which was also greater than any standard rational smaller than one. \(\square\)

Finite Additivity

We can trace the cause of the result in the last section back to the countable additivity condition. To show this, we construct a finitely additive measure which fulfills many of our desiderata and is supported on standard theories.

Definition 2. Define the set \(\mathcal{N}\) to be the set of all standard theories. A \(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi}\subset \mathcal{N}\) is defined as \(\mathcal{N} _{\varphi}:=\{T:\varphi\in T\}\). We define the base theory \(T_0\) as \(T_0:=\bigcap \mathcal{N}\).

Definition 3. Define a function \(\mu\) such that \(\mu(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi}):=\mathbb{P}[\varphi]\).

Theorem 2. Existence of Finitely Additive Measure Supported on Standard Theories. \(\mu\) is well-defined, finitely additive, and satisfies a version of the reflection principle: \[a < \mu(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi}) < b \Rightarrow \mu(\mathcal{N}_{P(\dot a, \ulcorner \varphi \urcorner,\dot b)}) = 1.\]

Proof. We first show that \(\mu\) is well-defined. By consistency of the reflection principle, we have that there exists a coherent, reflective \(\mathbb{P}\) over our base theory \(T_0\).

Say that \(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi}=\mathcal{N}_{\psi}\). Then, by definition, \(\varphi\) and \(\psi\) are in exactly the same complete theories, so \(\varphi\leftrightarrow\psi\) must be logically valid. Therefore, by completeness, \(T_0\) proves \(\varphi\leftrightarrow\psi\), so by Gaifman coherence, \(\mathbb{P}[\varphi]=\mathbb{P}[\psi]\). Hence, \(\mu\) is well defined.

We now check that \(\mu\) is a finitely additive measure. Clearly, \(\mu(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi})\in[0,1]\) and \(\mu(\emptyset)=\mathbb{P}[\bot]=0\). We need only check that it is finitely additive. \[\mu(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi}\cup \mathcal{N}_{\psi})=\mu(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi\vee\psi})=\mathbb{P}(\varphi\vee\psi)\]

If \(\mathcal{N}_{\varphi}\cap \mathcal{N}_{\psi}=\emptyset\), then \(\neg(\varphi\wedge\psi)\) is logically valid, so, by completeness, \(T_0\) proves \(\neg(\varphi\wedge\psi)\). Thus, by Gaifman coherence, \[\mathbb{P}(\varphi\vee\psi)=\mathbb{P}(\varphi)+\mathbb{P}(\psi).\]

By the way we defined it, \(\mu\) clearly satisfies the modified reflection principle we gave. \(\square\)



NEW LINKS

NEW POSTS

NEW DISCUSSION POSTS

RECENT COMMENTS

[Delegative Reinforcement
by Vadim Kosoy on Stable Pointers to Value II: Environmental Goals | 1 like

Intermediate update: The
by Alex Appel on Further Progress on a Bayesian Version of Logical ... | 0 likes

Since Briggs [1] shows that
by 258 on In memoryless Cartesian environments, every UDT po... | 2 likes

This doesn't quite work. The
by Nisan Stiennon on Logical counterfactuals and differential privacy | 0 likes

I at first didn't understand
by Sam Eisenstat on An Untrollable Mathematician | 1 like

This is somewhat related to
by Vadim Kosoy on The set of Logical Inductors is not Convex | 0 likes

This uses logical inductors
by Abram Demski on The set of Logical Inductors is not Convex | 0 likes

Nice writeup. Is one-boxing
by Tom Everitt on Smoking Lesion Steelman II | 0 likes

Hi Alex! The definition of
by Vadim Kosoy on Delegative Inverse Reinforcement Learning | 0 likes

A summary that might be
by Alex Appel on Delegative Inverse Reinforcement Learning | 1 like

I don't believe that
by Alex Appel on Delegative Inverse Reinforcement Learning | 0 likes

This is exactly the sort of
by Stuart Armstrong on Being legible to other agents by committing to usi... | 0 likes

When considering an embedder
by Jack Gallagher on Where does ADT Go Wrong? | 0 likes

The differences between this
by Abram Demski on Policy Selection Solves Most Problems | 1 like

Looking "at the very
by Abram Demski on Policy Selection Solves Most Problems | 0 likes

RSS

Privacy & Terms